Home
AL MAGHRIB
WHO I AM
RESUME (CV)
UC BERKELEY ACADEMIC WRITING
LA CITY COLLEGE (LACC)
"VOLKSWAGEN AND THE GERMAN MIRACLE" UC BERKELEY CLASS
BERKELEY FRIENDS
HIGH SCHOOL FRIENDS (taifata)
IMAGES OF BULGARIA
OTHER PHOTOS
ARTSY STUFF
FRIENDS' SITES
FAVOURITE LINKS
CONTACT
AUTOMOTIVE
ZERO GRAVITY
7. INTEGRATION OF EUROPEAN CITIZENSHIP: EXTENDING SOCIAL MEMBERSHIP

George Vassilev

UC Berkeley

PEIS 140

Prof. Meinolf Dierkes

10.01.2002

 

The question of European citizenship cannot be dealt with simply by using the terminology and concepts of national citizenship.  By virtue of its supra-national nature, the European Union cannot, by definition, provide a form of citizenship that is strictly identical to a traditional concept of citizenship.  The several layers of citizenship, present in the EU, are in dynamic relation to each other and are thus symbiotic, feeding off of each other.  The supra-national level cannot simply mimic the existing national concept.  Thus, conceiving of the notion of European citizenship, one has to redefine the concept of citizenship itself. 

First of all, one has to examine the question whether European citizenship really exists and if so, what forms it takes.  The treaty of Maastricht of 1992 introduced European citizenship in article 8 as an operational concept, stating that "Citizenship of the Union shall complement and not replace national citizenship" (Norbert Reich, 299).  Furthermore, article 17 of the treaty of Amsterdam elaborated on that statement and introduced the current wording relating to citizenship of the Union.

At present, the concept of EU citizenship is predominantly based on the right of free movement within the Union which benefits the economic citizen (or the Bourgeois), not so much the non-economic citizen (or the Citoyen) who would benefit from a social approach to citizenship, claims Reich.  Alongside the free movement rights, Europeans enjoy other standard rights of citizenship, such as voting in or standing for election at the municipal level or the right to grieve with the Ombudsperson.

However, this does not present a coherent and comprehensive citizenship model that equates different strata of the European community.  Rather, it expresses the Neo-Functionalist approach, favoured in the process of Euro-integration that focuses on harmonizing markets and balancing the aggregate economy in the expectation of spill-over benefits to other sectors of policy, public and personal life.  As noted before, this creates a cleavage between the economic and the non-economic citizen, which favours the former and largely disregards the latter at this level of Union integration. 

Thus Reich distinguishes between two levels of citizenship, the Legal and the Social ones, corresponding to the rights of the Bourgeois and the Citoyen respectively.  Legal citizenship is not an autonomous concept, it is argued, like residence or discrimination.  Rather, it is defined in terms of a member state's legislation.  The concept of Social citizenship follows one of two paths.  The rights path looks for what specific rights beyond the existing ones will be extended on the supra-national level.  This approach faces a growing area of uncertainty; to be precise, how will rights be stretched to protect nationals of one member state in another.  The rationale that seems to underlie this is to protect "fundamental community objectives of market integration rather than to protect individual rights per se" (Reich 303).   Once again, the cleavage between the Bourgeois and the Citoyen appears.  Regardless, extending rights is a growing tendency, which can be construed as a positive development.  

The status path, on the other hand, focuses on the horizontal extension of rights to all citizens and residents, an approach supported by global trends.  Due to increased mobility, distribution of subjective rights is on the basis of legal residence, not citizenship.  This nowadays widely accepted practice extends many rights to members of other states legally residing in a country, except for the provision of direct political entitlements and certain kinds of employment.  This approach seems to be the most challenging because of the problem it would create in the treatment of members of third countries.  It would present an additional level of complexity to the already complicated European social policy dimension.  Namely, what entitlements should be distributed to a citizen of a third country that chooses to employ the right of free mobility within the European Union as a resident of one of the member states.  Employment would be a huge obstacle, voting at all three levels of authority (the local, the national and the supra-national) would become close to impossible to arrange.  Also, natural EU citizens would like to impede immigration as they face a rigid labour market often coupled with a shortage of social services and hyper-urbanization.  Furthermore, if social services such as education, health care or pensions are extended to residents under the same conditions as citizens, this would create huge immigration and budget problems.  Lingering chauvinism should also not be disregarded. 

Within codifying and developing Social citizenship lies the heart of the matter.  European citizenship, very much like the Union itself, is a work in progress.  Unless it is fundamentally defined, the concept and indeed the reality of EU citizenship would not be fully functional.  Scholars, such as Marie Jose Garot, cited by Reich (305), try to decouple nationality and citizenship and extend full rights to denizens (lawful residents, who are not citizens of any member state) because she believes they contribute as much as citizens to the welfare of the communities they reside in. 

Furthermore, social citizenship does not only entail the provision of human rights and access to welfare and other public benefits but should also imply a set of duties and responsibilities, a side of social policy that has gotten minimal attention in EU legislation, if any at all.  But are these feasible at the current juncture?  Until now, Reich states, "Union citizenship has remained a metaphor with some added value."  (Reich, 308)

Once that the lack of a social dimension on the EU level is identified as the main obstacle to implementing a functional concept of EU citizenship, it is necessary to examine the different types of Social Citizenship.

            One approach to defining it is through the concept of Residual Social Membership.   This is "a federation of autonomous and sovereign states possessing only minor supra-state competence (where) social rights guaranteed by the EU are minimal"   (Thomas Faist, 312).  The arguments in support of this view on Social Citizenship state that the EU has primarily dealt with market-making and compatibility issues since its contrivance.  As a result, EU social rights have become effective in very few areas- workplace safety regulation and gender equality are among them.  However, "the core issues of wage bargaining are still excluded from EU competence: remuneration, the right to strike, and labour union rights." (Faist, 313) 

In opposition to this view, it must be pointed out that the treaty of Amsterdam (1997) has the formal definition of fundamental human rights; fundamental social rights are defined in the Charter of Social Rights 1989. Also, cooperation in the social services sphere has been in place in a lot of European countries prior to joining the EMU in the late 1990s.  This model overlooks the scheme that social citizenship is distributed throughout the multi-level governance system of the EU; a fundamental approach toward building the EU as a whole.

Another approach to Social Citizenship is that of Post-national Social Membership.  Its main postulate is that the great inter-and supra-state mobility present in today's world and in the EU specifically requires that denizens and citizens rights have to be merged.   This issue, described in detail above is plagued by the problem of redistribution.  As meritorious as it is on the plane of democratic treatment of the issue, this approach would remain purely theoretical for a long time in the foreseeable future.

Perhaps the most promising approach toward understanding and resolving the issue of European citizenship is the Nested Social Membership model.  It clearly reflects the institutional setup of the EU, and it manages to deal with the dynamic relationship between the different levels of authority.  Nested Social Membership resides in multiple sites; in "an interactive system of politics, policies, and social rights between the sub-state, state, inter-state and supra-state levels." (Faist, 314)  It implies multiple levels which mirrors the political structure of EU institutions altogether.  It also implies a sort of federative membership as a cumulative phenomenon, not merely an additive one (which is the essence of multiple citizenship).  Furthermore, it adequately represents the reality of sharpened tension between third state members and proper EU citizens.

Since "most analysts take the model of a sovereign state as the final destination for European integration "(Faist, 315), it is necessary that all constraints to its achievement be recognized.  Euro-optimists have identified certain deficits in achieving social integration of European citizenship.  

The Solidarity Deficit, they claim, must be overcome since it is necessary to rally resources to reduce social exclusion on an aggregate European level. But is it really essential since in the past, welfare institutions developed first and solidarity came afterward?  The weak point of the argument, according to Faist, is that the causal arrows usually run both ways.  That statement, in turn, also provides a source of doubt because if causality is directed both from the dependent to the independent variable in this model and vice versa, then it is very likely there is only a correlation involved and not causality.

            The Cultural Deficit concept states that Europe is devoid of a cultural framework independent of the nation state.  This is not necessarily true because there are different sentiments for or against Europeanization in different member states.

A key ingredient in the allocation of legitimacy to the different layers of authority in the EU is borrowed from the Catholic doctrine of Subsidiarity, and transformed into the contemporary category of Devolution.  In other words, power is delegated to the lowest level of competency that can exercise it.  This encourages the idea of Multi-level governance but it is sometimes hard to identify the proper institution to be charged with a particular task.

Still, the practical difficulty remains for Europeans to reconcile their national and regional sense of identity with the all-European, which is the project of policy implementation and rational contrivance.  In a study of German and French attitudes toward the integration of the national with the supra-national identity, Joachim Schild notes that "a national identity should not be construed in opposition to a European one and vice versa."  (Schild, 324).  According to studies on the matter by Eurobarometer since 1982 France and Germany, often seen as polar on the issues of public support for the integration process (where France presents a fairly nation-centric attitude, while Germany boasts energetic support for it), German enthusiasm has been steadily declining during the 1990s.  This is possibly due to the rallying of resources to strengthen the central level of authority, where Germany has been the major investor in terms of finance, institutional leadership and expertise.  There is a certain renewal of regional collective identities in the Basque country, Lombardy, Flanders, Scotland, Wales.  The above suggests that there is "growing importance of cost-benefit considerations for the sense of European identity" (Schild, 327).  That is, unlike the sense of local or national identity, which are essentially sentimental, the feeling of European-ness is dependent on what the development of the EU gives in addition to, or takes away from the local and national identity, expressed in terms of benefits.  With the common currency in circulation and performing well for about a year, it is interesting whether transcending local and national identity has been eased.  In an electronic interview, carried out for the purposes of this research paper, Mr. Schild notes that

 indeed...the Euro does change things. It will enhance the European identification of those citizens whose countries are members of the Euro-zone. But it will not improve the legitimacy of the whole EU as there will be a number of member states in an enlarged EU which won't be members of the Euro-zone in the near future.

Further, Mr. Schild points out that "the antiquated notion of a common culture has to be complemented, though not entirely replaced, with European citizenship as a common project." (Schild, 318). 

Now that European citizenship has been codified in the Treaty of Amsterdam and the different facets of it have been defined, it is apparent that citizenship of the European Union cannot be in any sense a mechanical construct based on traditional notions of identity and citizenship.  The concept of EU citizenship is dispersed along the lines of the local, national and supra-national levels of political legitimacy, just as all other levels of authonomy within the Union.  Belongingness to the united Europe is generally viewed through the prism of cost and benefit to the local and the national levels.  Thus, in unison with rational choice theory, the citizens of the member states would support a drive to unifying European citizenship and all which it entails only if that would bring additional benefits at a reasonable cost. The following logical step in bringing that closer to reality is a focus on definition and operationalization of Social Citizenship which would eliminate asymmetries between the different member states in the provision of transfer payments, health care, educational financial assistance and all other forms of social services.

 

 

 

BIBLIOGRAPHY:

 

 

1. Eurobarometer   URL:  http://europa.eu.int/comm/public_opinion/

 

2. Faist Thomas, University of Bremen,  Social Citizenship in the European Union: Nested Membership, Journal of Common Market Studies, March 2001, Vol. 39

in  Dierkes, Meinolf, PEIS 140, Europe in Transition: Can its Institutions Adapt?, UC Berkeley, 2002

 

3. Reich, Norbert, Union Citizenship- Metaphor or Source of Rights, European Law Journal Vol. 7, No.1, March 2001, Blackwell Publishers, Malden, MA, USA

in  Dierkes, Meinolf, PEIS 140, Europe in Transition: Can its Institutions Adapt?, UC Berkeley, 2002

 

4. Schild, Joachim, Deutsch- Franzosisches Institut, National v. European Identities? French and Germans in the European Multi-Level System, Journal of Common Market Studies, June 2001, Vol. 39, No.2

in  Dierkes, Meinolf, PEIS 140, Europe in Transition: Can its Institutions Adapt?, UC Berkeley, 2002

 

5. Schild, Joachim, interview 09.29.2002, joachim.schild@swp-berlin.org, Dr. Joachim Schild Stiftung Wissenschaft und Politik, Forschungsgruppe I: Europäische Integration
Ludwigkirchplatz 3-4 10719 Berlin, Tel: + 49 30 88007-202 Fax: -100

 

Enter supporting content here